Table of Contents
What exactly is the problem with the University of Oklahomaâs âAnti-Racist Rhetoric & Pedagogiesâ workshop?
The University of Oklahoma chapter of the American Association of University Professors released a statement responding to our reporting on the universityâs for First-Year Composition instructors.
The statement â and subsequent commentary from chapter members â attacks FIREand criticizes our analysis of the workshop. Revealingly, the critics have not tried to defend the actual statements made in the workshop. Rather, they defend the workshop broadly by projecting the stated goals of OUâs First-Year Composition curriculum without regard to what was actually taught in the workshop.
In fact, the OU AAUPâs description of the curriculumâs goals is so divorced from the workshopâs actual contents that one has to wonder if the OU AAUP actually watched the same video that we did.
âDerogatory remarks, critiques, and hate speechâ and âwhite supremacist ideas or sourcesâ
The OU AAUP says this of the composition curriculum upon which the workshop is based:
The assignments are carefully crafted to invite students to write about issues that matter to them. The goal of the assignments is to help students understand how to speak and write to those who think differently from themselves--to explore multiple sides of an issue and to research how stakeholders of that issue are invested in it. ALL students must explore an issue from multiple sides, whether their initial position is progressive or conservative.
These are admirable liberal arts goals. But, the thing is, students here are being taught the opposite: that they canât âexplore multiple sides of an issue.â The workshop advises that students navigate veritable trip wires of forbidden and ill-defined thought and expression. One instructor endorsed banning âderogatory remarks, critiques, and hate speech,â as well as âwhite supremacist ideas or sources.â That instructor does so without ever defining what any of those terms mean.
The history of speech codes on American college campuses is littered with endless examples of well-meaning college officials using precisely these kinds of vague and general terms to police thought and expression on campus. And since there is rarely an agreed-upon definition of these terms, they necessarily invite arbitrary and ideological enforcement.
Letâs take âwhite supremacy,â for example. Some argue that American policing is a white supremacist institution. Is using certain law enforcement sources, such as crime data, off-limits then? What about generally supporting the police? The vice president of the OU AAUP, Julie A. Ward, who has been in opposing ĂÛÖÏăÌÒâs conclusions about the workshop, Oklahoma Gov. Kevin Stitt last year for wearing a neck gaiter, which she said represents âa racist symbol of white supremacy.â What about former President Donald Trump? He has been said to represent white supremacy, including by . Can students not cite the former president in their papers?
The generalities used in the workshop conveniently evade any direct answers to these questions. Ward herself seems to understand the chilling effect of generalities as applied to expression: In writing about that addresses how issues of race and gender can be taught, primarily in K-12 institutions, Ward notes that the law is âworded so generally as to discourage any discussion of race or gender in the classroomâ â a claim with which FIREhappens to agree.
Where the disagreement seems to lie is whether this particular workshop trains instructors to cross the line from instruction into indoctrination.
But Wardâs concern doesnât seem to extend to the vague speech codes the workshop recommends for OUâs writing courses. And the consequences for students are real: One workshop leader remarked that if students donât avoid these forbidden âideas and sources in their work,â instructors can tell the students, âNo, you do not have the right to say that. Stop talking right now.â If that doesnât work, she says, âReport them for violating the Student Code of Conduct.â
These punitive responses forgo valuable teaching opportunities that would show students how more speech and robust discussion of complex and controversial topics can lead to stronger arguments and better ideas. Instead they shut down hard conversations before they start.
As this article was about to go live, one of the workshop instructors, Kelli Pyron Alvarez, in which she insists that she defines these terms and âoffer[s] examples of what they look likeâ to her students. But she does not provide her readers any of those examples, making it impossible to investigate her claim. As for definitions, she has this to say:
I remind my students that, because they should be engaging in good-faith research and responses throughout the semester, they need to avoid obscenity, which is defined by Miller v. California (1973) as work that âtaken as a whole, lacks serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific value.â Essentially, any argument that invalidates or seeks to impede someoneâs basic human rights or their identities is not an acceptable argument for students to make, as it lacks political and scientific value and is in direct opposition to basic human rights.
That argument is nonsensical. Miller applies only to depictions or descriptions of sexual conduct, which her readers would know if she didnât selectively quote the test the Court used to identify âobscenityâ in that case. The test, among other things, limits obscenity to work that âdepicts or describes, in a patently offensive way, sexual conduct [emphasis added] specifically defined by the applicable state law.â The Miller case has zero to say about an âargument that invalidates or seeks to impede someoneâs basic human right.â
From instruction into indoctrination
Letâs turn to the next argument in the OU AAUPâs statement. It cites historian Joan Scott to contend that:
the constraints upon free speech that govern classroom discourse are legitimized by the professorâs own academic disciplinary authority. Such constraints are not demands for âsilent acquiescence in the face of indoctrinationâ; rather, they are the basis for training in critical thought, a training that will ultimately empower students to âquestion orthodoxy and challenge it from a position of knowledge rather than one of unexamined beliefâ.
Despite the statementâs suggestions to the contrary, thereâs nothing in this argument with which we disagree. In fact, we spent an entire section of our reporting on this workshop discussing and defending those freedoms, writing that instructors:
have wide latitude to manage the atmosphere and tone of the classroom. This may include inhibiting some student expression in class by directing classroom discussions, prompting students to write on topics of the instructorâs choosing, and preventing students from disrupting the class or talking out of turn.
We recognize and accept the necessary authority of instructors to exercise academic and pedagogical freedom within their classrooms. Unfortunately, much of the OU AAUPâs criticism of ĂÛÖÏăÌÒâs reporting omits this understanding, with the chapter president and vice president falsely claiming that FIREadvocates for ââ or an ââ
Instruction becomes indoctrination âwhen instructors dogmatically insist on the truth of such propositions by refusing to accord their students the opportunity to contest them. Indoctrination occurs when instructors assert such propositions in ways that prevent students from expressing disagreement.â
Where the disagreement seems to lie is whether this particular workshop trains instructors to cross the line from instruction into indoctrination.
The AAUPâs 2007 report argues that âIt is not indoctrination when, as a result of their research and study, instructors assert to their students that in their view particular propositions are true, even if these propositions are controversial within a discipline.â
But, critically, the report then goes on to state that instruction becomes indoctrination âwhen instructors dogmatically insist on the truth of such propositions by refusing to accord their students the opportunity to contest them. Indoctrination occurs when instructors assert such propositions in ways that prevent students from expressing disagreement.â
Does the workshop in question not do precisely that when it advises instructors to tell students âwho might be, like, entertaining the idea of listening to a problematic argumentâ that âwe donât have to listen to thatâ?
Or what about the real-life example from one of the workshop leaders in which a black student told her they wanted to explore Black Lives Matter? The leader reported telling the student, âThat is not an issue that I would take up. [Black Lives Matter is] not an argument. Itâs a fact, right? . . . You are not obligated to entertain or listen to an argument that is trying to tell you that your real experiences are not real, because the person making the argument has never experienced them.â
What about the workshopâs suggestion that students can only explore certain sources if they are used to advance a particular ideological goal: to âdismantleâ white supremacy?
Workshop attendees share ĂÛÖÏăÌÒâs concerns
Questions posed by attendees echoed ĂÛÖÏăÌÒâs concerns that the workshop was veering too far away from discussing the proper exercise of an instructorâs pedagogical freedom and into the realm of thought reform and indoctrination. Both questions asked during the workshop voiced these concerns.
One questioner asked whether âweâre quick to dismiss what we might construe as, like these harmful topicsâ or whether there are âtopics or stances that we might be a little too quick to dismiss as dehumanizing.â
Another questioner asked about pronouns. They note that the ârightâ that people have to insist that others use certain pronouns when addressing them isnât a right enshrined in the Constitution, and itâs being actively debated. âWhat do we do with those [topics] where the debate is still out there on whether something is a right or not?â
According to one instructor, students can write about the pronoun debate, but only if they come to the âacceptableâ conclusion:
If theyâre writing and their goal is like âOh, I should be able to use whatever pronouns I deem acceptable for this person despite how they identify,â then they are invalidating that personâs humanity and their existence. And thatâs not acceptable. So I flat out tell them that. This is what this is doing. You need to pick something else. Because youâre not doing that.
Again, taking guidance from the AAUPâs , thatâs indoctrination, not instruction. Are the instructors here not âdogmatically insist[ing] on the truthâ of certain contestable propositions? Are they not ârefusing to accord their students the opportunity to contest themâ?
We further agree with the AAUP that, âIdeas that are germane to a subject under discussion in a classroom cannot be censored because a student with particular religious or political beliefs might be offendedâ â which nevertheless seems to be the precise impetus for the workshopâs advice to its attendees.
âDemocratic pedagogyâ
The OU AAUP statement then argues that:
F.I.R.E.âs claim about âindoctrinationâ assumes that college-level humanities instruction can be reduced to a binary model, one in which all knowledge can be encapsulated in the form of âquestionsâ which have two âsidesâ for which one might abstractly advocate in turn. In rejecting this simplistic binary, the instructors of the âAnti-Racist Rhetoric and Pedagogyâ workshop speak from the perspective of democratic pedagogy and are backed by the tradition of academic freedom.
To be fair, I am not quite sure exactly what the OU AAUP is suggesting here, but exploring multiple sides of issues is part of a liberal education. It also happens to be what the OU AAUP claims is the purpose of First-Year Composition: to âexplore multiple sides of an issue.â The alternative is the âpall of orthodoxy,â the placing of certain âquestionsâ as off-limits (the scare quotes around âquestionsâ are the OU AAUPâs â not ours).
One instructor said students can write about the pronoun debate, but only if they come to the âacceptableâ conclusion. Taking guidance from the AAUPâs own report, thatâs indoctrination, not instruction.
The statementâs contention that the workshopâs instructors speak from the perspective of âdemocratic pedagogyâ is also confusing. The statement doesnât define âdemocratic pedagogy,â but a July 2008 journal article by Sheryl MacMath entitled argues that it envisions âclassrooms of open dialogueâ in which âall human beings are morally equal, we are all capable of intelligent and well-informed opinions, and we can solve any problem if we work collaboratively.â
This sounds pretty admirable, but it does not sound anything like the classroom environment the workshop instructors advocate here, where they tell students to âstop talking right nowâ if they make the wrong argument, recommend referring students for discipline if they trip over various vague and ill-defined classroom speech codes, and see it as their responsibility to prevent students from even âentertaining the idea of listening to a problematic argument.â
The president of the OU AAUP joins the conversation
Before closing out, I want to take a minute to address critical of our position, this one from OU AAUP President Michael Givel, entitled âĂÛÖÏăÌÒ!â
Givel argues that:
The main gist of ĂÛÖÏăÌÒâs deeply flawed argument is that free speech includes the absolutist right to espouse any racist, sexist, and homophobic comments in a classroom. In a way this is also an argument that a student has the right to be a racist or sexist or homophobe in the classroom. I have taught for a long time in the classroom, and such vile utterances are and would and could be a major recipe for ongoing hyper-acrimony and disruption of the learning process itself. It is tantamount to opening the gates to continual classroom chaos and anarchy.
To be clear, and as we stated earlier, FIREdoes not advocate for an âabsolutist rightâ for students to say anything they want in the classroom. Thatâs a straw man argument. At risk of beating a dead horse here, ĂÛÖÏăÌÒâs classic âGuide to First-Year Orientation and Thought Reform on Campusâ states that â[a] professor may have ground rules to ensure civility and order, and a professor should insist upon mastery of a subject (while protecting a studentâs right to reasoned dissent), but a professor has no right to demand ideological uniformity.â
The problem with OUâs workshop is that it instructs teachers on how to restrict academic arguments, not disruption. For example, it advises teachers not to allow students to explore the Black Lives Matter movement or pronoun debate in a class that specifically invites students to âwrite about issues that matter to themâ and encourages them to âexplore an issue from multiple sides, whether their initial position is progressive or conservative.â
Instructors in such a course should not get to arbitrarily label certain arguments âracist, sexist, and homophobicâ and proclaim them off-limits. This is part-and-parcel of what FIREPresident & CEO Greg Lukianoff calls the : determine what categories of speech â or even speakers â are off-limits, and then put any ideas you donât want to listen to within those categories.
We should also note that when it comes to whether a student âhas the right to be a racist or sexist or homophobe in the classroom,â the answer to that question is that yes, students have the right to hold whatever opinions they choose to hold. While Givel may be using this as a shorthand for expressing opinions in class rather than simply holding them (we hope), itâs important to remember that, as bad as it is to tell someone they may not say something, itâs far worse to tell them that they may not even believe it.
âShouting fire in a theatreâ
Which brings us to Givelâs next argument: That allowing the âcontinual . . . chaos and anarchyâ of free speech in the classroom âis like, well, shouting fire in a crowded movie theaterâ:
The analogy of shouting fire in a crowded movie theater was enshrined into law with the 1919 US Supreme Court case of Schenck v. United States. In the Schenck case, the US Supreme Court ruled that words that cause a mass panic like in a crowded movie theater are not protected under the First Amendment. There is a state role in balancing the interests between absolutist free speech and public safety and causing a significant mass panic or altercation. The prohibition altercations [sic] was later upheld in the US Supreme Court case of Brandenburg vs. Ohio in 1969.
This might be the for censorship that exists. Itâs regularly trotted out to justify censoring everything from a play about comedian Lenny Bruce to . Pick an idea you want to censor and then claim expressing that idea is like âshouting fire in a crowded movie theater.â
But these would-be censors often fail to understand the history â or even the actual wording â of their preferred metaphor. For one, Givel leaves out the very important âfalselyâ caveat to âshouting fire in a theatre.â Nobody argues that one shouldnât shout âfireâ if, in fact, there is a fire.
For another, Schenck v. United States (1919) is rightly regarded as an abomination of justice: Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes Jr., in his majority opinion, compared the handing out of anti-draft leaflets during WWI by a group of socialists akin to âfalsely shouting fire in a theatre and causing a panic.â It was on this logic that Holmes justified Charles Schenckâs arrest for speech that today is soundly protected by the Constitution. One might reasonably argue that there was indeed a very crowded theatre, so to speak, in Europe at the time and some claims of âFire!â were warranted. And even then, Holmes himself changed course on the question only a few months later, (along with Justice Louis Brandeis, another free-speech luminary) in Abrams v. United States (1919).
Regardless of what I or anyone else thinks of the Schenck case, the powers granted to the state by the Espionage Act of 1917 and ratified by the Supreme Court in that case were powers meant to be exercised during wartime. Unless Givel thinks his classroom is akin to a battlefield and student arguments about Black Lives Matter akin to burning draft cards, I suggest he abandon the âfire in a theatreâ metaphor.
For a more comprehensive look at the widespread misuse of the âfalsely shouting fire in a theatreâ analogy, I recommend Ken Whiteâs article,
A final note about speech codes
Givel goes on to say, âNews flash. Absolute free speech that includes hate or hateful speech that intimidates and harasses is not permitted in a college classroom at OU. Not in the slightest.â
âWe have a student misconduct code,â he says, âAbusive conductâincluding intimidation, harassment, and humiliationâis prohibited, per se.â
Yes, we are aware of OUâs speech codes. We catalogue them and give them a âyellow light ratingâ because they âtoo easily encourage . . . administrative abuse and arbitrary application.â
Whatâs more, Givelâs claim seems to miss decades worth of concern around speech codes and the way their vagueness and overbreadth invite censorship and a chilling effect. This is a concern shared by the AAUP in its 1992 statement :
In response to verbal assaults and use of hateful language, some campuses have felt it necessary to forbid the expression of racist, sexist, homophobic, or ethnically demeaning speech, along with conduct or behavior that harasses. Several reasons are offered in support of banning such expression.
[. . .]
But, while we can acknowledge both the weight of these concerns and the thoughtfulness of those persuaded of the need for regulation, rules that ban or punish speech based upon its content cannot be justified.
Givelâs right about one thing, though. Unlawful harassment â properly defined â is rightfully prohibited. And professors have wide latitude to restrict inside their classrooms what otherwise would be considered constitutional expression outside their classrooms.
But, again (Is the horse properly dead yet?), neither we nor OUâs workshop leaders were talking about student expression that would rise to the level of unlawful threats, harassment, or discrimination. Such behavior would be vanishingly rare in any college classroom in the country. Actual disruptions and unlawful speech were not at the center of the workshop â indoctrination and thought reform were.
But again, you donât have to take our word for it. Thereâs a video (and a transcript!), so you can watch it and decide for yourself.
Recent Articles
FIREâs award-winning Newsdesk covers the free speech news you need to stay informed.