Table of Contents
âHarvard Crimsonâ Column: Time to Get Rid of Academic Freedom
Harvard University student Sandra Y.L. Korn has a in The Harvard Crimson that has been making the rounds. The column has a bold thesis: We should get rid of academic freedom as our standard for what ideas should be admitted to the university sphere, and replace it with what she terms âacademic justice.â In Kornâs concept of academic justice, âWhen an academic community observes research promoting or justifying oppression, it should ensure that this research does not continue."
The concept of academic freedom Korn seeks to supplant is long-established and enshrined in, among other statements, the American Association of University Professorsâ (AAUPâs) 1940 Statement of Principles of Academic Freedom and Tenure, which has been adopted by scores of universities. Academic freedom is not absolute, of course; it exists within the standards of the academic profession. But it can be understood as largely objective in nature, a broad protection for academic research, teaching, publication, and speech designed to be free of political interference and the tyranny of the majority.
âAcademic justice,â on the other hand, is necessarily a nebulous concept, subject to the whims of what its self-appointed guardians determine to be right and true. Though she doesnât wholly flesh it out, Korn gives us a couple of concrete examples of how academic justice should work in practice:
The power to enforce academic justice comes from students, faculty, and workers organizing together to make our universities look as we want them to do. Two years ago, when former summer school instructor Subramanian Swamy published hateful commentary about Muslims in India, the Harvard community to ensure that he to teach on campus. I consider that sort of organizing both appropriate and commendable. Perhaps it should even be applied more broadly. Does Government Professor Harvey Mansfield have the legal right to publish a book in which he that âto resist rape a woman needs ⊠a certain ladylike modesty?â Probably. Do I think he should do that? No, and I would happily organize with other feminists on campus to stop him from publishing further sexist commentary under the authority of a Harvard faculty position. âAcademic freedomâ might permit such an offensive view of rape to be published; academic justice would not.
FIRE decried Swamyâs firing, Torch readers may remember, as an attack on free speech and academic freedom that devalued the Harvard name. It should surprise no one reading this blog that FIREwould say that stripping Professor Mansfieldâs academic freedomâmandating that, as a Harvard professor, he is allowed to express only certain opinions on gender and other topicsâwould devalue it far further. Why? Because like the AAUP and countless institutions, FIRErecognizes academic freedom as playing a fundamental role in, among other things, advancing human knowledge. Whatâs more, the protection academic freedom affords teaching and research has played a substantial role in helping our thinking on matters of race and gender evolve, a point that seems lost on Korn when she asks:
If our university community opposes racism, sexism, and heterosexism, why should we put up with research that counters our goals simply in the name of âacademic freedomâ?
This question should answer itself. The function of âbadâ ideas is to bring into greater clarity the comparative validity or persuasiveness of âgood ideas,â which provides us the information we need to choose the proper course. Rigorous testing of our ideas, and being forced to articulate why we believe them, can only serve to make us better and more informed.
Kornâs case for âacademic justiceâ is quite similar to the cases put forth for establishing âhate speechâ laws that curb free expression, as well as many of the defenses of campus speech codes. The argument posits that there are opinions and ideas out there that, if spoken or publicized, harm listeners. Why shouldnât we be able to censor such expression and punish those responsible for it? Just like the case for hate speech laws, the case for academic justice falls into the same trap.
For one, a regime of academic justice would surely demand fealty to a legion of nebulous concepts over which people disagree wildlyânot the least of which is the notion of "justice," which has been intensely debated for thousands of years, frequently at the cost of tremendous loss of human life. Just as the Supreme Court famously declared in Cohen v. California, 403 U.S. 15, 25 (1972) that âone manâs vulgarity is anotherâs lyric,â one manâs idea of âjusticeâ may vary significantly from anotherâs. This does not mean that one is right and one is wrong. Yet it seems safe to say that there is one acceptable concept of justice in Sandra Kornâs framework, and that is Sandra Kornâs. FIREhas seen where this leads before. Columbia Universityâs Teachers College, for instance, has litmus-tested students in part on how they conformed to Columbiaâs concept of âRespect for Diversity and Commitment to Social Justice.â The University of Delaware forced students in its residence halls through a coercive, invasive âtreatmentâ program where they were forced to adopt highly politicized positions on sensitive topics.
Another major obstacle to this kind of value-based system is that such systems nearly always establish hazily-realized ideals as rules and trust their enforcement to those in positions of power. Proponents of such measures tend not to see much problem with this, because it is hard for them to imagine anyone having values different from their own. But values change over time. (See gay marriage, or gun control, or marijuana legalization.) Consensus dissolves. Minority positions become majority positions. And eventually, sea changes in public opinion are reflected in those holding positions of influence, who may hold opinions quite different from yours. To accept the systemâs place in regulating speech and thought is to accept the fact that it may one day decide it no longer has any use for your ideas and that it may take away your right to express them. You can protest your disenfranchisement but only at the cost of your credibilityâbecause, after all, this is the system you wanted in the first place.
Hence the danger of Kornâs position that â[o]nly can take the moral upper hand,â when dismissing bipartisan criticisms of the American Studies Associationâs decision to boycott Israeli institutions. Kornâs argument presumes we have all the answers and can therefore stop asking the questions. It takes the position that âbadâ speech should be silenced, rather than challenged with more speech. In that respect, Kornâs âsocial justiceâ framework is no different from any other form of censorship.
In short, it â,â asking us to trade it for a very particular idea of justice. Itâs a trade we shouldnât make.
Image: "Red Book on Deck" -
Recent Articles
FIREâs award-winning Newsdesk covers the free speech news you need to stay informed.
Ayaan Hirsi Ali will not submit
Podcast
Ayaan Hirsi Ali grew up in a culture of conformity. She was beaten and mutilated. She was told who she must marry. Eventually, she rebelled. "You don't speak up at first," she told us. "First you leave and you find a place of safety. It's...